Tuesday 22 March 2016

The Paradox of Freedom (5) - Austrian Thought and the Crisis of Liberalism

Image credit. Attersee, Austria - where we used to spent the summer holidays. The lake is 20 kilometres in length. My father calculated that the view from one end of the lake to the other is blocked by a water hump about 8 meters in height.

Continued from here.



14.4 Conscious Design, Intermediary Conditions, and Spontaneous Order

Man lives in a world of intermediary conditions (see section 2.1) that challenge him to exercise his rational faculties so as to align his means to his purposes. Behaviour attempting and organised around rational anticipation is itself a product of evolution. In this way, conscious design is built into a world that proves to be largely a spontaneous order looked at from distant enough a vantage point. The principles of liberalism as well as the principled behaviour needed to maintain a liberal order are ultimately delivered by acts of purposive behaviour and conscious design, which in other instances may at the same time also be the source of more or less rational, yet groping experimentation, or fully unintended negative or positive consequences. The relationship of conscious design to outcomes engendered in a spontaneous order is subtle and multifaceted. It is not exhaustively captured by a simple dichotomy. Spontaneous order being essentially an experimental event, human experimentation is part and parcel of it, and not always destructive of it, regardless of whether more or less successful at predicting its likely results. For us to discern which features of a spontaneous order are useful and deserving of careful application and protection, we are again dependent on the human ability of conscious judgement and design. Hayek’s policy proposals – currency competition, the bicameral legislature, his concept of a private law society  ‑ are unadulterated examples of conscious design. Tolerant and considerate behaviour, action aiming at trust, cooperation, and give-and-take, requires premeditated stratagems – conscious design in other words. By contrast, it appears that the Hayekian habit of thinking in terms of SO1 breeds secondary habits such as reflexive dismissal of conscious design and an obsession with impersonal mechanisms of the market type or other variants incorrectly thought to operate without being vitally tied to politics and the state.

15. Liberalism between Harm Principle and Benefit Principle[1]

More generally, where does one draw the line between the inactive liberal harm principle and the activist benefit principle, the latter calling for coercive public measures – engendered, incidentally, within the tradition of the common law – that, at the cost of restricting personal freedom, bring about benefits for all, thus at least presumptively lifting all ships at once? At what point is liberty being fatally compromised? Has the welfare state led to a secular decline in liberty? If not, why? Can we expect people to shun the new social technology, the modern state with its unprecedented command of resources? Is freedom really indivisible? Is freedom so rigid as not to be amenable to contextually dependent suspension of certain of its aspects, even some of her principles? Of course, in a sense, liberty is indivisible in that for her to prevail we need to apply certain principles in general (equality before the law). In another sense, liberty is not indivisible: think of the redefinition of bundles of rights that in a free society permanently takes place both in the world of commercial transactions and in the political sphere (abolition of slavery, female suffrage, gay rights etc). Considering these constraints and avenues of advance, are the options for the development of liberty susceptible to valid treatment by a uniform concept of liberalism? Do not liberals disagree on these issues? Is not freedom turning liberalism into an ambiguous concept, naturally sparking a fierce competition of meanings?

The classical liberal legal scholar Richard Epstein, the very man accusing Hayek of socialism, argues passionately in favour of pursuing the benefit principle and recommends the paradigm of the social contract to be applied as a means of imitating the win-win outcomes of private contracting by public coercive policies, when such benefits are impossible to attain from voluntary transactions.

The social contract theory is not, it has been said, worth the paper it is not written on, and modern efforts to work out that theory have all emphasized the hypothetical nature of the consent that drives the underlying transaction. But just because the obvious theories fall short, do we reject (in the name of the free market, no less) all forms of taxation and regulation? For most people the answer is no: political obligation there must be-strong enough to account for a state and its power to tax, but not so strong as to leave nothing left to individual discretion and control. […] That’s where the benefit principle comes into its own, and the language of social contract gains its lasting intellectual force. […] In an ordinary contract, two elements are conjoined: the parties each have consented to the new package of rights and duties, and each benefits from that exchange. With complex social settings, the notion of consent is jettisoned, but the central ideal of contract – joint gains – remains. The system, therefore, is social insofar as it represents a grand construct that is imposed on individuals and is not chosen by them, but it is contractual insofar as it imitates the distribution of net gains that any system of voluntary contracts presupposes. [2]

16. Undercurrents of Freedom

The emergence of order from causes that form hard-to-detect undercurrents beneath the surface of appearances is a characteristic feature of the processes that lend stability and effectiveness to spontaneous systems. The paradox of freedom suggests that liberty has a concealed depth-structure and operates in large measure without the benefit of detailed management and immediate political support. Extending the paradigm of spontaneous order to politics and the state is apt to shed light on the hidden depth structure of freedom and the potential as well as the limits of her self-generating nature.

16.1 Freedom as Method (II)

Epstein’s approach points in the direction of what we call “freedom as method.” Namely, the search for methods and institutions that promote positive-sum-games in a society where value-diversity is admitted and high levels of personal autonomy are aspired to as a presumptive condition of peaceful existence and high productivity.

This contrasts with “freedom as model” or “freedom as blueprint.” In our reading (see section 12.), freedom is not the projection of a complete world – like the three dimensional, detailed model of, say, a city to be built – or more generally: a system that is at some conceivable stage (a) complete and (b) can be anticipated and prescribed in its completeness.[3] Freedom as method is rather a barrier of caution, a way of asking critical questions that help us guard against error, dysfunction, and accident? Freedom as method seeks to filter out restrictions on personal liberty that issue in zero-sum-games and negative-sum games, while admitting such restrictions that create win-win situations in the private as well as the public sphere.


[1] According to the harm principle, the protected domain of the individual may not be infringed upon, except to defend against illegitimate force and fraud. The benefit principle, however, admits of more extensive infringements, if the latter are necessitated by the common weal, i.e. a substantial public advantage requiring qualified and controlled transgression, with those infringed upon receiving just compensation for curtailment of their rights.
[2] Epstein, R. (1998), pp. 124-125.
[3] In criticising certain presumed violations of freedom some libertarians as if a world of no such violations were feasible, ignoring the fact that freedom requires fallible experimentation, compromise, and changes in relative political dominance. In this way, liberal criticism often implies freedom as model or freedom as blueprint, i.e. a state of affairs in which no presumed violation of freedom occurs and freedom is realised in exhaustive fullness.

Continued here.

No comments:

Post a Comment