Thursday, 14 January 2016

[Summary] - Government, the State, and Freedom (5) - John Gray's Account

Image credit.Continued from Government, the State, and Freedom (4) - John Gray's Account
Summary and Conclusion of the sequence Government, the State, and Freedom.


The state is built around rights, which logically precede it, rather than the state being the originator of these foundational rights. If we look at the state as a conduit of democratic pressures, however, we may well regard it an originator of rights. However, this implies that a process of self-government is productive of the rights – not the discretion of an aloof institution levitating over the people. In a word: sovereignty is invested in the people and imparted upon the state as the custodian of popular sovereignty.

For the state to act as the people’s steward, it needs to be tied to rules not of its own discretionary making, that limit its range of operation and competence.

The liberal conception of the state as custodian of popular sovereignty implies limited government.

Popular sovereignty also implies a tension between limited government (constitutionalism) and self-government (democracy) which I shall be dealing with in a sequel to “Precommitment …

Limited government is not necessarily tantamount to a demand for minarchism, which latter requires a small state confined in its competences to the protection of rights and the upholding of justice.

The temptation to interpret limited government as small government, however, reveals an inherent indeterminacy in the liberal conception of the state. The rights on which liberalism insists are double-edged in the sense that on one hand they are simple and clear in their meaning, whereas on the other hand they are open-ended and contestable – just think of “contractual freedom.” The "lucid," easy to understand and endorse  edge of this sword seems to imply that all the ramifications of this particular right are obviously connected with its lucid part and that therefore there are unequivocal answers to whatever further questions there may raise. But this not so. The base of a liberal consensus on liberal rights does not extend too far into their practical ramifications. All the more, as the system of liberal rights is multi-nodal with many different rights requiring a balancing of their core demands with myriads of interpretable implications. Liberal principles quickly become an impetus "instigating" a pluralist discourse that cannot, in their turn, be decided by recourse to a uniform set of liberal principles. Thus the liberal concept of the state is really the starting signal for a broader political competition in which liberal principles are but one of many inputs. This also elucidates what I mean by robust conditions of freedom – these are liberal principles that are accepted by the entire pluralist community, including non-liberal partisans. In so far as some of their implications and readings are contested, they are non-robust, malleable, often even non-essential and disposable.

The soft belly of liberal rights, the more opaque or indeterminate or non-robust part of them that is open to diverging interpretations invites an expansive vision of the state. Put differently: since the robust conditions of freedom do not provide an impenetrable frontier blocking interpretations that entail expanded state competences, over time people will focus on extensions of the state that show promise to enhance their interests (while respecting by and large the robust conditions of freedom. 

Minarchism is an illusion. And limited government is not a prescription for an exclusively liberal understanding of government. Amenable to competing construal, in certain respects liberal rights simply do not vouchsafe anything that could be called THE LIBERAL STATE, a uniquely liberal institution. Believing in liberal rights is like standing in a fog, where the immediate surrounding is clearly visible, while what lies further away becomes increasingly hazy (= subject to different interpretations).

In the first part of the sequel, I also note that public perception of liberalism is focused on extreme variants: the monarchism propagated by many of liberalism's most visible exponents, on the one hand, and modern (American type of) liberals, on the other hand, who may be called illiberal to the extent that they substantially discount the need to keep government controlled by criteria of state limitation. But then again, these criteria are subject to the “fog effect,” whereby the degree of illiberalism in granting larger scope to the state is not always easy to establish.


Does freedom require a specific type of government or is she to be achieved under different forms of government: I tend to emphasise that for practical reasons freedom is not enduringly possible without democracy, while logically she does not seem to be defensible in the absence of political freedom –meaning, what is “free and equal” supposed to mean when there is a class of citizens that may determine the political fate of society and another that is barred from exerting political influence? A society without political freedom (defined as the possibility of every citizen to participate in political competition) cannot have limited government, because not all citizens are empowered to define and protect their rights - the privileged rule setting by a caste of "law makers" resulting in arbitrary impositions on a subordinate class of mere "law takers."

In a word: it is inscribed into the liberal conception of the state that neither the state nor freedom at large are going to be an exclusively liberal project.


Whereas in the first sequel I tried to work out the two zones of liberal implications: the core zone of robust conditions of freedom, which are clear, liable to enlist widespread understanding and support, and the more diffuse zone - farther removed from the core zone -, in which the choices that we need to make among potentially correct implications ramify to become numerous not rarely rival branches. The strength of the core convictions quickly peters out when it is confronted with practical questions entailing multiple contestable implications.

Here, now, I emphasise the ideological allure to which the liberal may succumb in replacing logic by aesthetics. It is possible to make the world fit my premises by virtue of biasing my perception conveniently to replace fact-controlled logic with harmony-controlled aesthetics. The ideologically tempted liberal takes the inner resonance of her theory as the ultimate test of its validity, rather than its resilience in standing up against implacable facts. Among the multiple contestable implications, the liberal chooses the one’s that imbue her theory with harmony.


Here I examine another stage in the transformation of liberal principles into ideological preconceptions – the abuse of fetishist patterns. I pay particular attention to the liberal desideratum of non-arbitrariness. Again, we are dealing with a robust condition of freedom that is starkly obvious in certain situations, but does not preserve this success as a general quality to be applied to any number of different situations. In a word: the insistence of non-arbitrariness can mutate into a fetish, a misapplied criterion. And again, the reason why the criterion loses its magic touch is that situations may occur where non-arbitrariness entails multiple contestable implications or no clear implications at all, or only very vague and provisional ones. These issues must be sorted out on their own merits rather than with reference to the spurious assumption that certain principles are of uniform applicability.

In conclusion:

The liberal theory of the state exposes the narrow limits of any uniform account of the state. It teaches us a lesson concerning the temptations and dangers awaiting a doctrine that overestimates the universalisability of its premises. In looking at the liberal theory of the state we arrive at one of the many battles in which liberalism tries to escape its inevitable fate as the actuator of its own demise – or shall we say: diffusion into an amalgam of competing views that mutually affect their evolving meaning.

No comments:

Post a Comment